000 | a | ||
---|---|---|---|
999 |
_c33407 _d33407 |
||
008 | 241105b xxu||||| |||| 00| 0 eng d | ||
020 | _a9780571226030 | ||
082 |
_a700.1 _bCAR |
||
100 | _aCarey, John | ||
245 | _aWhat good are the arts? | ||
260 |
_bFaber and faber, _c2006 _aLondon : |
||
300 |
_axiv, 296 p. ; _bill., _c20 cm. |
||
365 |
_b609.69 _c₹ _d01 |
||
504 | _aIncludes bibliographical references and index. | ||
520 | _aIn What Good are the Arts? John Carey - one of Britain's most respected literary critics - offers a delightfully skeptical look at the nature of art. In particular, he cuts through the cant surrounding the fine arts, debunking claims that the arts make us better people or that judgements about art are anything more than personal opinion. Indeed, Carey argues that there are no absolute values in the arts and that we cannot call other people's aesthetic choices "mistaken" or "incorrect," however much we dislike them. Along the way, Carey reveals the flaws in the aesthetic theories of everyone from Emanuel Kant to Arthur C. Danto, and he skewers the claims of "high-art advocates" such as Jeannette Winterson. But Carey does argue strongly for the value of art as an activity and for the superiority of one art in particular: literature. Literature, he contends, is the only art capable of reasoning, and the only art that can criticize. Language is the medium that we use to convey ideas, and the usual ingredients of other arts objects, noises, light effects - cannot replicate this function. Literature has the ability to inspire the mind and the heart towards practical ends far better than any work of conceptual art. | ||
650 | _aArt criticism | ||
650 | _aAbstract art | ||
650 | _aAesthetic | ||
650 | _aArtistic artworks | ||
650 | _aConceptual art | ||
650 | _aEpigenetic rules | ||
650 | _aMass art | ||
650 | _aPopular art | ||
650 | _aVisual cortex | ||
942 |
_2ddc _cBK |